DRAFT
version, posted on the internet for the purposes of scholarly exchange. Comments welcome. Please contact author for permission to quote or distribute. -- gws
Just
Policing:
How War Could Cease to Be a Church-Dividing Issue
Gerald W. Schlabach
University of St. Thomas
All
these considerations compel us to undertake an evaluation of war with an
entirely new attitude.
Second Vatican Council[1]
Defining
effective international government in this way is of course setting an
idealistic goal; but it is less idealistic than the idea that military action
could be truly an instrument of justice.
John Howard Yoder[2]
This paper is a
thought experiment. It does not claim
that we are upon the threshold of Christian unity vis-à-vis war quite yet. Rather, it is an exercise in imagining the
“conditions for the possibility” of reaching that threshold. It seeks to chart how just war and pacifist
Christians might converge enough that a new horizon would come into
view, wherein we might then see more clearly how war could cease to be a
church-dividing issue. Some such
convergence may be possible if together we explore a conceptual territory that
long-standing debates between pacifists and just war thinkers has left surprisingly
unmapped. Joint examination of policing,
I suggest, may point us towards conditions for the possibility of agreement
vis-à-vis war.
War:
Can We Have It Both Ways?
Virtually every
Christian tradition is trying to have it both ways on war. This may be a sign of honest puzzlement, or
it may be a sign of diplomatic fudging, but it is surely one sign of unfinished
agenda.
The Roman
Catholic Church has long been custodian of the Christian tradition of just war
deliberation, which began when Saints Ambrose and Augustine used arguments from
Roman thinkers like Cicero in order to justify some wars while disciplining all
wars. Since the Second Vatican Council,
however, the Catholic Church has also given a new level of recognition to vocational
pacifism, at least.[3] In the early 1980s, U.S. Catholic bishops
writing on The Challenge of Peace explicitly paired the traditions of
just war and pacifism or active nonviolence as legitimate Christian responses
to war.[4] Three years later, Methodist bishops in the
U.S. made a similar affirmation of both traditions in their statement In
Defense of Creation, insofar as each serves “as a partial but vital
testimony to the requirements of justice and peace.[5]
Historic peace
churches (Mennonite, Church of the Brethren, Society of Friends) certainly do
not recognize the legitimacy of just war thinking with an easy reciprocity that
would mirror these statements by “mainstream” Christian traditions. Yet in their own way, peace churches have
found that they too must “have it both ways” by acknowledging the need for
someone, somewhere, to use potentially lethal violence to preserve order in a
fallen world. In the formative years of
the sixteenth-century Radical Reformation, the Schleitheim Confession of 1527
gave this recognition classical expression for Mennonites by speaking of “the
sword” as “an ordering of God outside the perfection of Christ;” accordingly,
“secular rulers” are “established to wield” the sword that “punishes and kills
the wicked” but “guards and protects the good.”[6]
Even when
representatives of just war thought and pacifism have collaborated and discovered
how much they already agree upon, the difficulty of “having it both ways” may
remain and actually become more striking.
A case in point is the Just Peacemaking initiative that gathered 23
Christian ethicists annually during much of the 1990s and articulated “ten
practices for abolishing war.”[7] The 23 scholars found much consensus by
bracketing debates over theory or principles and instead identifying practices
that are obligatory for all Christians.
For those identified with just war teaching these are practices that
Christians must seriously engage before resorting to warfare if any claim of
“last resort” to military action is to be meaningful. For pacifists, these are practices that require positive
engagement lest the “non” in “nonviolence” imply passivity at worst or mere
protest at best.
With its focus
on concrete practices, the Just Peacemaking approach offers a major precedent
for the approach I will be exploring below.
Yet at one point their consensus proved particularly fragile. According to the introduction to Just
Peacemaking: Ten Practices for Abolishing War, all participants agreed to
include among their “ten practices”
humanitarian military invention to halt egregious human rights abuses, yet not
all were sure they could actually affirm it.[8] The problem, one suspects, was that for the
pacifists in the Just Peacemaking initiative to affirm such a practice
unambiguously would seem to have meant assent to a stringent, limited and thus
rectified just war approach -- but a just war approach nonetheless.
Even so, the
Just Peacemaking initiative certainly moves us forward in at least three
ways. First, by focusing on practices,
the initiative reminds us of the path by which many Christians are already
creating “conditions for the possibility” of convergence concerning war and
peace, and how they should continue to do so.
Second, attention to practices may further offer a way to deal
constructively with remaining differences without underestimating or
suppressing them. After all, if
Christian practices cannot or should not be identical --insofar as every Christian
community thrives on a diversity of gifts and callings, according to St. Paul--
then we will need to pay close attention to what Christian communities must
actually do in order to discern authentic vocations from God. And that may in turn allow us to reduce the
differences in practice among currently divided Christians to vocational
ones.
But third, even
as the Just Peacemaking initiative has revealed its point of weakest consensus
it has also marked out a continuing point of agenda: Is policing different enough from war that something more
like policing (humanitarian military intervention) could possibly constitute a
practice for abolishing war?
The difference
between war and policing does make a difference. So I will argue. Policing seeks to secure the common good of the very society
within which it operates; because it is embedded, indebted and accountable
within that community it has an inherent tendency to minimize recourse to
violence. Warfare may also seek to
secure the common good of a society, of course; but because it extends beyond
that society through threats to other communities it has an inherent tendency
to cut whatever slender bonds of accountability would truly limit its use to
“last resort.” And this difference is
only the beginning, for having cut loose, war usually jeopardizes not only the
common good of international community, but even that of the society in whose
name it is being waged.
Neither
pacifists nor just warriors have explored that difference adequately.[9] If they would do so together and thus
all-the-more accountably, however, war might in fact cease to be a
church-dividing issue. How so? If both attended more fully to the difference
between war and policing, then (1) what once was claimed to be “just war” would
finally be just because it would just be policing not war; (2) pacifists could
fulfill not betray their vocation to call all Christians to the nonviolent way
of Jesus Christ by helping societies respond more effectively to the challenges
that have historically led to war; and (3) in the process both would have
practically yet decisively rejected war.
To begin moving in this direction, however, both traditions of moral
reflection need to recognize their respective failures to think in clear and
forthcoming ways about policing.
Policing
and the Just War Tradition
The just war
tradition of moral deliberation suffers from a kind of slipperiness.[10] The claim that war can sometimes be morally
justifiable, and the tradition of rational reflection that attempts to limit
war to morally justifiable exceptional cases, gets much of its credibility by
imagining war to be like police action.
It thus seems mere “common sense" that war may sometimes be
necessary to protect innocent third parties and maintain order between nations,
just as police force does within a given community. Once wars have been justified in this way, however, very
different psycho-social dynamics take over, which move it farther and farther
away from policing.
The intention
of the just war theory’s more conscientious developers and proponents has been
to keep violence at the bare minimum that human societies apparently need if
they are to maintain order in a sinful world.
Beginning with a strong presumption against violence, which the
tradition shares with pacifism, just war thinkers would allow recourse to
lethal violence only as an exception and only as a concession to the realities
of our world. Ours is a world, after
all, that does not yet enjoy the fullness of God’s Reign but instead suffers
from crime, unjust aggression, exploitation, abuse of human rights, and thus
from a general lack of mutual trust. In
such a world, love of neighbor and protection of the innocent seem at times to
require the judicious use of violent force.
To be moral and judicious in fact, any recourse to violent force must
come only in the wake of sincere attempts to resolve conflicts and sanction the
recalcitrant by first using other kinds of force. Only when the criterion of last resort and other criteria are met
may war be justifiable.[11]
Yet skeptics
have reason to wonder whether just war reasoning delivers upon its promise to
limit the violence of war. John Yoder
once recounted a well-placed incident that represents all too well the way in
which just war reasoning loses whatever grip it had on Christian conscience and
devolves into something else. Yoder was
in the lecture hall at the University of Basel around 1951 when Karl Barth
delivered lectures on war that would later go into volume III/4 of his Church
Dogmatics. As Barth condemned
virtually every rationale for war and declared that pacifism is “almost
infinitely right,” his students squirmed -- until, at the last moment, Barth allowed
an exception: A Christian republic like
his own Switzerland might fight a strictly self-defensive war. First came a palpable release of tension,
then applause. “What is significant
here,” noted Yoder, “is the difference between what Barth said and what the
students understood.” Barth had
condemned all but the rarest war, he later came to oppose nuclear weapons
categorically, and he even called himself “practically pacifist.” Yet “every half-informed Christian thinks
Karl Barth is not opposed to war.” If
theologians are going to claim their positions are realistic, concluded Yoder,
they must acknowledge that this “tendency of theologians’ statements to be
misinterpreted is also part of “political reality.”[12]
Just so, just
war reasoning all too often devolves functionally into propaganda. It becomes permissive rather than stringent;
it sometimes becomes permissive precisely through the reassuring guise of
having been stringent. It serves to
condone wars by establishing the general principle that wars can be
just. Its best-intended practitioners
may wish to curtail wars through rigorous moral deliberation over particular
wars. But that is not the message that
reaches the pews. Just war deliberation
should require disciplined (even heroic) political action when particular
wars fail to meet just war criteria. If
that is not happening, what we have here is a just war rhetoric or theory or
intellectual tradition. What we do not
really have is a just war tradition in the full communal sense -- a
living tradition with operative practices shaping a community through time.[13]
Yet despite
these failures just war thinking continues its hold on moral discourse because
it seems to make simple “common sense.”
We need not rehearse the principles and precepts of the natural law (in
accord with Catholic just war thinking) in order to notice why.[14] All we must do is notice a telling
phenomenon: Non-pacifist Christian thinkers
may treat the need for the police function as self-evident and needing no
argument,[15]
or they may sometimes argue at length for the legitimacy of the police function
based in biblical texts such as Romans 13 and 1 Peter 2,[16] and in
either case they may then go on to argue analogically for the legitimacy of
Christian participation in warfare using the police function as a metaphor --
but they never do the reverse and use war as a metaphor for policing.
The point here
is not that there is complete discontinuity between the role that civic
authorities take in ordering the life of communities through the police
function, and the role that they play in protecting those communities through
the military function.[17] If the core arguments of this paper prove
convincing and fruitful, Christians will need to discriminate carefully among
the continuities and the discontinuities in war and policing on their way
toward eliminating war as a church-dividing issue. The point for now is simply that the easy assumption of
continuity, based on using policing as a metaphor to explain the workings of
war, obscures some very serious differences between policing and war. That obscurity in turn keeps the just war
tradition from working -- even on its own terms.
For once war is
justified as an extension of the self-evident need for policing, war consistently
becomes something other than policing, and the just war tradition tends to
devolve into either “war realism” or crusading. War realism” (alternately, “warism”[18]) is the very
position that the just war theory has tried to disprove, namely, that war has a
life and logic all its own, impervious to moral considerations.[19] Crusading is the real dynamic that drives
putatitively just wars whenever their defenders cite just cause to the exclusion
of all other criteria for a just war, whenever unconditional surrender is
demanded, whenever the preservation of personal or national honor keeps people
fighting long after they have reasonable grounds to expect “probable success,”
or whenever claims to righteous causes or sacred duties trump in any other way
the demands that just war criteria would impose.[20]
In all of the
following ways war takes on a very different psycho-social dynamic from policing:
1. The
rally-‘round-the flag phenomenon.
Political leaders draw on the rhetoric of national pride, honor and
thus crusading in order to marshal the political will and sustain the sacrifices
necessary to fight wars, even if their deliberations initially ran the war
through the grid of just war criteria.
This is the phenomenon we associate with phrases such as “rally around
the flag” and “war fever.”[21]
2. The blunt
instrument problem. Even circumscribed
warfare, aiming to meet the criterion of noncombatant immunity, is too blunt of
a tool to serve the police officer’s basic task of identifying and apprehending
criminals.[22] The very need to appeal to the principle of
double effect in order to explain why a nation and its soldiers are not
blameworthy when their targeting results in “collateral damage” amounts to a
tacit recognition of this problem.
3. Failure to meet
minimal requirements for the rule of law.
War can never be subject to the rule of law in the way that policing can
be. As Stanley Hauerwas notes, in good
policing the “arresting agent is not the same as the judging agent,” but in war
“those two are the same.”[23] If the development of democratic processes
since ancient Greeks teaches us anything it is that no rule of law is possible
without separating the roles of “judge and executioner,” as the saying goes, or
better, judge and arresting agent.
4. The football
phenomenon. Coaches and generals both have reasons to
insist that the “best defense is a good offense.” But those then become reasons why “good” military strategy intrinsically
tends toward greater and greater firepower while “good policing” inherently narrows
the use of violence to last resort. If
the best defense is a strong offense, then striking hard and striking first
make sense. Very quickly, however, key
just war criteria such last resort, proportionality and noncombatant immunity
lose out.
5. Adrenaline rush. We have words like “frenzy,” “berserker” and
“berserk” in the English language precisely because our linguistic ancestors
noticed what the heat of battle can do to the psyche of warriors.[24] Irrationality sets in. Warriors simultaneously experience deep fatigue
and intense focus, power and vulnerability, love of comrade and hatred of
foe. Amid this volatile psychological
mix they may strike indiscriminately, continue against impossible odds (i.e. improbable
success), and survive by drawing on every emotion that Augustine’s theory of
“right intention” amid war would rule out.
Those who do not “go berserk” need the rush of adrenaline to survive;
those who guide their battles from far from the front lines vicariously feel
that rush.[25]
6. The
let-them-not-have-died-in-vain phenomenon.
Even if one no longer has good reasons to be at war, and even if that
war never passed the muster of just war criteria, the death of one’s forebears
or comrades in an otherwise untenable war gives “reasons” to fight on. For although the defense of honor is not a
just cause in the canon of just war criteria, in the collective mind of any
general populace it is probably the most forceful reason to fight.[26] This and the adrenaline phenomenon
consistently make it unimaginable for a nation to sue for peace, even though
surrender should be a moral obligation whenever one’s own war effort
fails to meet the criteria for a just war.[27]
7. Militarization. The more that a civilian population and a
military force engage with one another, the more violent and indiscriminate
warfare becomes.[28] Militarizing civilian populations makes them
more vulnerable to attack, makes it harder for the military’s enemies to fulfill
the criterion of noncombatant immunity, and tends to weaken the social fabric
by obscuring the deeper causes of conflict and injustice while offering
military solutions to social problems.
On the other hand, the more that a community and its police are engaged
with one another the less violent policing can become. “Community policing” is a new name for a return
to an old strategy that gets police out of their patrol cars, onto the street,
into town meetings, and integrated into the neighborhoods they seek to protect.[29] Police cannot do it well without attending
to the deeper causes of crime and thus strengthening the social fabric of a
community.
This list is
probably not unassailable and surely not exhaustive.[30] Critics might note counter-evidence pointing
out psycho-social continuities between policing and war, while sympathizers may
extend the list and corroborate it with further research.[31] Still, the list should be sufficient to
demonstrate that, contrary to long usage, policing cannot serve in any kind of
facile or automatic way as a metaphor to justify warfare. For the just war theory to stand any chance
of fulfilling its advocates’ best intentions, it must retrace its steps and
attend far more closely to the ways in which war is not like policing at
all. “Just war” is probably a misnomer
for what can only be just policing if it is to establish a real tradition of
actually reducing violence to the minimum possible for a fallen world.
Policing
and the Pacifist Tradition
What pacifists,
or at least Mennonites, think about policing is no more clear, however. They are not likely to find early Anabaptist
thinkers making clear distinctions to guide them here, because 16th-century
magistrates combined the roles of police and warrior.[32] Twentieth
century Mennonites have directed most of their attention against military
conscription, militarism and warfare.
Their answer to why Mennonites would not be police officers was
sometimes that Christians have more important things to do. This does, however, carry the intriguingly
implication that while their pacifism vis-a-vis military action was principled,
their pacifism vis-à-vis police action was vocational.
Which brings us
to September 11, 2001. The al Queda
terrorist attack that day upon New York’s World Trade Center and the U.S.
Pentagon certainly did not “change everything” for Christian believers
who know that Calvary is the day that changed everything.[33] And yet Sept. 11 certainly has
dislodged neglected issues of all sorts and forced even people of firm faith to
examine their assumptions anew. For
Christians committed to the thoroughgoing practice of nonviolence, the place of
policing is one of those issues.
Strikingly,
after all, the best immediate alternative to vengeful retaliation that many pacifist
voices could advocate was that nations treat the Sept. 11 attacks as a crime
against humanity and try terrorists in courts of international law. On September 22, the MCC Executive Committee
issued a statement that focused on upholding “the call of Jesus to love enemies
and live as peacemakers” while praying for and reaching out to people affected
on all sides of the conflict. Following
the exhortation of Jeremiah 29:7 that Israelites exiled in Babylon should “seek the welfare of the city,” the statement reiterated that
the primary citizenship of Jesus’ followers means living “as citizens of a new
Kingdom,” yet also means being “advocates and builders of peaceful systems and
institutions” wherever they live. What
then to advocate? While praying for
national leaders, people of faith should “call on governments to exercise
restraint and respect for the process of international law and diplomacy.”[34]
Pacifist
theologians, ethicists, and international specialists made similar moves. Mennonite ethicist Duane K. Friesen urged
students and colleagues to view Sept. 11 within a crime framework not a war
framework.[35] Veteran Mennonite peacemaker John Paul
Lederach[36]
called for a multifaceted response that would address root causes and
strengthen the international system; still, his proposals did include recourse
to the United Nations or Islamic courts of law, and explicitly, “domestic and
international policing.”[37] Theologian Stanley Hauerwas, a pacifist ally
of Mennonites, said he would like to start envisioning ways to take the police
function into the international arena, so long as societies learn to do a
better job of providing local police with the resources and social cooperation
they need to make killing a truly rare event.[38]
What broad
appeals to international courts of law do not always clarify, however, is who
would apprehend the criminals, how they would operate, and whether the
political bodies that conduct international policing would have the support of
pacifist churches.[39] Jim Wallis, editor of Sojourners
magazine, stated the problem clearly.
He had advocated “the most extensive international and diplomatic
pressure the world has ever seen against bin Laden and his networks of terror
—- focusing the world’s political will, intelligence, security, legal action,
and police enforcement against terrorism.”
Such mobilization would dry up the terrorists financially and politically,
and expose their “ugly brutality” before an international tribunal. “But when the international community has
spoken, tried and found them guilty, and authorized their apprehension and
incarceration, we will still have to confront the ethical dilemmas involved in
enforcing those measures. The
terrorists must be found, captured, and stopped. This involves using some kind of force.[40]
Wallis was not
simply ceding to the claims of that amoral school of international relationships
known as Realpolitik, nor to Christian Realism so-called. The editorial stance of his magazine and his
article as a whole make clear that his first priorities remained policies to
focus on the conditions of global inequity and superpower hubris that breed
resentment and terrorism, initiatives that utilize culturally-sensitive
conflict resolution of the sort Lederach practices, and strategies that develop
forms of force which remain compatible with nonviolence. True “realism” would recognize that these
may be the only ways to combat rather than breed terrorism, after
all. Nonetheless, Wallis was squarely
facing the fact that even a society that did everything he as a longtime peace
activist was calling for would still require the police function (for further
demonstration of this point, see Appendix
B). Thus we must press the question
of whether post-9-11 calls for turning to international legal procedures do not
imply positive support for police action.[41]
Though
Mennonites have not been much more forthright about policing than just war thinkers,
there are precedents both in Mennonite practice and among leading Mennonite
thinkers for seeing policing as a different question than war and soldiery --
leading to different possible answers.
Within and among the “historic peace churches” that have opposed
Christian participation in warfare and militaries, the same level of consensus
does not exist concerning Christian participation in policing.[42] Mennonite institutions such as colleges,
with responsibility for the security of hundreds of residents, have quietly
cooperated with local police -- and even the strongest advocates of nonviolence
on their faculties have rarely objected.
Along with a general trend among Mennonites to label themselves as
“nonviolent” or “pacifist” rather than “nonresistant,” and in turn to accept
nonviolent direct action as compatible with Jesus’ teachings, Mennonites have
been leaders in developing nonviolent alternatives to the criminal justice
system. Parallel to the work of John
Paul Lederach in international conflict transformation, Mennonites such as
Howard Zehr have launched programs for victim-offender reconciliation -- with
restitution rather than retributive punishment as the judicially-recognized
consequence of crime wherever possible -- while helping provide a conceptual
basis for what many now know as “restorative justice.”[43]
Such efforts
have certainly gone forward in the same spirit as efforts to conceptualize and
then launch pilot projects in unarmed civilian-based defense, which would allow
nations to imagine and then begin the process of transarmament away from the violent
weaponry upon which their militaries depend today -- but there is one subtle
difference. That difference might allow
Mennonites and other pacifists to participate in policing institutions in a way
that they cannot conscientiously do within military institutions. It is this:
On one hand,
military transarmament would require military institutions to become something
qualitatively other -- organizers and mobilizers of the broad civic participation
needed to make societies unconquerable, with last resort recourse only to the
potentially lethal force of true policing on the international level. On the other hand, transarmament for the
criminal justice system requires police institutions to do a better job of what
their mandate is already to do -- preserve community order and secure the
safety of all citizens with only rare, minimal, and judicious use of
violence. In short, nonviolent
strategies for responding to international conflict constitute alternatives to
war that would displace the military as we know it, while nonviolent strategies
for reforming the criminal justice system simply make the police into better
and better police. Thus, cooperation
with and eventually within the policing system could be imaginable for
Christian pacifists in a way that working within the military system is
not.
Even when
leading Mennonite thinkers have explained why they believed faithful Christians
could not serve as police, they have offered precedents for thinking the question
of policing through to a different answer.
At mid-20th century, Guy F. Hershberger’s no to policing was
clear. The state is ordained by God
according to Romans 13, but as a “sub-Christian” measure that God provides for
a sinful world.[44] When pressed that police operations “may be
necessary for the successful operation of a state in a sinful society,”
however, Hershberger’s simplest and in some ways most elegant answer was that
“the Christian is called to live a life on a higher level than this” and thus
has better things to do by witnessing to Christ in word, deed, and ministries
of reconciliation.[45]
Within a few
years John Yoder would identify the question of calling as potentially decisive,
but would on principle refuse to decide -- because deciding must be the
case-by-case task of discerning communities who hold their members accountable,
offer them binding pastoral guidance in particular historical circumstances,
and make those judgments by the Christian community’s own standards of gospel
proclamation[46]
not
by a reading of the “natural” order that is so easily confused with the limited
standards of a fallen world.[47] Like Hershberger, Yoder was prepared to
affirm the legitimacy of the state, with its police function, as God’s provision
to limit evil in a world estranged from God.[48] And though far readier to approve of
Christian political advocacy,[49]
Yoder
certainly agreed with Hershberger (and early Anabaptists) that God’s ordering of
the state did not automatically warrant Christian participation in
the state.
Yoder, however,
used this basic Anabaptist-Mennonite framework to make somewhat different
points. Affirming the legitimacy of the
police function provided a wedge for more pointed critiques of war and
militarism. Since the biblical standard
for judging a magistrate’s legitimacy was protection of the innocent and
punishment of the guilty, “the state never has a blanket authorization to use
violence.”[50]
Indiscriminate warfare and the use of war for
any purpose beyond “the localized readjustment of a tension” are therefore
“wrong for the state, not only for a Christian;” though limited police action
within society or by the United Nations could not be condemned in principle,
“all modern war” stood condemned “on the realistic basis of what the state is
for.”[51] While keeping Christian social ethics
focused primarily on witness to Christ’s reconciling lordship according to the
standards of Jesus’ gospel proclamation of God’s Reign, Yoder was widening that
focus enough that Mennonites could recognize social and political engagement to
promote social justice and limit violence as part of this very
witness.
Having
suggested that limited police actions --domestic or international-- might not
be condemned in principle, however, Yoder then needed to revisit the question
of whether a Christian could be a police officer. Characteristically, his
answer reframed the question:
The
question, May a Christian be a policeman? is posed in legalistic terms. The answer is to pose the question on the
Christian level: Is the Christian called
to be a policeman? We know he is called
to be an agent of reconciliation. Does
that general call, valid for every Christian, take for certain individuals a
form of a specific call to be also an agent of the wrath of God?[52]
If Yoder was
moving the discussion of policing from the domain of principle to the domain of
vocational discernment, the immediate result was not to make it any more likely
that Christian pacifists would apply to become police officers.[53] Rather, Yoder drove home the point that the
conditions do not now exist to make this morally possible:
Stating
the question in this form makes it clear that if the Christian can by any
stretch of the imagination find his calling in the exercise of state-commanded
violence, he must bring us (i.e., lay before the brotherhood) the evidence that
he has such a special calling. Long
enough we have been told that the position of the conscientious objector is a
prophetic one, legitimate but only for the specially called few; in truth we must hold that the nonresistant position is
the normal and normative position for every Christian, and it is the use of
violence, even at that point where the state may with some legitimacy be violent,
that requires an exceptional justification.[54]
Yoder reported
never having met anyone “testifying to such an exceptional call.” But could he -- ever?
Nothing is
possible here if Christian communities lose their frame of reference -- the
Gospel, not the natural order except as known through the lens of Christ’s
revelation of its true character;[55] ministries of
reconciliation, not the functions of state except as used instrumentally to
achieve limited nonviolent ends; the mission of the Church, not the
self-interest of nations except perhaps as defined through the preferential
option for the poor and transnational solidarity. In other words, Hershberger and Yoder were right to insist that
as a rule Christians do have better things to do than police.[56] For even if exceptions to the rule exist they
are ordered teleologically to the end of Christian witness that defines the
rule.
Whatever is
possible here will require consistent practices for testing vocation of the
sort Yoder outlined before concluding that he knew no one who had passed the
test. And whatever practices of
accountability are possible will require churches in which nonviolence is the
norm for all their members. To envision such practices vis-à-vis policing we
can extrapolate from what Yoder recommended in a later speech for any
Christian who holds “a position of relative power in the wider society.” On one hand, such a person can only be
trusted in that role if they do not claim “autonomy in that station by virtue
of God’s having made it an authority unto itself,” but instead “will listen to
the admonition of his sisters and brethren regarding the way he discharges
it.” On the other side, the peoplehood
called Church should understand itself to be an ekklesia in the original
Greek sense with which the church of the Apostles adopted the word: “it meant
parliament or town meeting, a gathering in which serious business can be done
in the name of the kingdom.” Yoder was
proposing that discernment groups and accountability procedures become standard
practices so that the Church would not only “model” the kind of community God
intends for the world, but would offer “a pastoral and prophetic resource to
the person with the responsibilities of office.”
Sometimes
the function of the community will be simply to encourage him to have the nerve
to do what he already believes is right.
At other times, other church members, thanks to their participation in
other parts of society, will bring to his attention insights he would have
missed; sometimes the community’s proclamation of the revealed will of God may
provide for him leverage to criticize the present structures.
But in no case
would the public office become “autonomous as a source of moral guidance.”[57]
Practicing
for Just Policing
Let us be
clear: Should the concept of “just policing”
gain currency, the first task of advocates will continue to be resistance to
the militarization of currently constituted police forces. None of these arguments aims to affirm all
that goes by the name of policing, nor to encourage Mennonites and other
pacifists to join their local police forces as currently constituted, nor to
discourage Mennonites and Catholics alike from denouncing police brutality and
human rights abuses wherever they occur.
Nor is our intention to justify any nation taking on the role of “policeman
of the world,” which is actually a euphemism for imperialism, not international
police forces accountable to the rule of international law. The militarization of the police forces
poses real dangers in many urban areas of the United States, for example, where
racism and endemic social ills have too often conspired to place police on a
war footing vis-à-vis minority populations.
On one hand, all of the just war criteria for assessing whether the
exercise of violent force is acceptable should continue to apply for the
purpose of minimizing not rationalizing violence.[58]
On the other hand, pacifist work to
strategize alternatives to war and the overall criminal justice system should
not neglect the need for nonlethal and nonviolent tactics for apprehending and
detaining criminals. Thus, both
traditions have contributions to make simply in the improvement of ordinary
policing. In doing so, the patterns may
emerge by which war could cease to be a church-dividing issue.
Looking back,
two trends have already brought us to a point from which to envision a way
toward further convergence. Coming from
a direction that pacifists can recognize and own is the development of
nonviolent action. Coming from a
direction that non-pacifists can recognize and own is the development of
community policing.
As Tobias
Winright has pointed out, the development of efficacious nonviolent action for
political ends in the 20th century, coupled with a shift among pacifists toward
identifying their position as Gandhian nonviolent resistance rather than
Tolstoy’s nonresistance, has already begun to change the shape of
debates about policing: “With this type
of pacifism in mind, then, the efficacy of violence in policing, generally
assumed by nearly everyone [until recently], is called into question. That is, when the greater efficacy of
nonviolence is granted, policing itself can be envisioned in a completely
different way.”[59]
Converging from
the other direction is the model of “community policing.” By extending it into the international arena
Catholics may be able to fulfill the mandate of the Second Vatican Council to
“undertake an evaluation of war with an entirely new attitude,”[60]
to
make the enforcement of international law into “just policing,” to integrate
the contributions of pacifists have already been making to international
peacemaking, and to invite their further participation in “just policing”
without requiring them to condone warfare in exceptional cases.
Though the
concept of community policing is only a decade or two old, it has already
produced a large literature, with debates over both the best ways to implement
it and the worst case dangers that can come with its abuse.[61]
What makes it an appropriate model to extend
by analogy into the sphere of international policing is the way that it integrates
(1) the very sort of work on root causes of violence and conflict that
pacifists have advocated as basic for achieving real peace with justice, (2) a
continued but modified role for apprehending criminals, and (3) ample room for
developing less-violent and nonviolent tactics for even that apprehension. Community policing, wrote one commentator,
refers
to a shift from a military-inspired approach to fighting crime to one that relies
on forming partnerships with constituents.
It employs health and human service programs as well as more traditional
law enforcement, with an emphasis on crime prevention. It represents a change from a reactive model
of law enforcement to one dedicated to developing the moral structure of
communities.[62]
”Moral
structure of communities,” yes, and the web of community relationships that constitutes
healthy society.
But this in
turn is how analysts like Lederach would urge nations to respond to terrorism
-- holding criminals accountable to international law; strengthening the preventive
system by beginning the hard work of changing “patterns of political,
religious, and economic roots of social exclusion, isolationism, and oppression
that contribute to the origins of terrorism;” and integrating these immediate
and long-term approaches by relying upon (not resisting) the interdependence of
nation with nation.[63] Terrorism is not located in any one
territory, after all, notes Lederach.
Instead it uses “the power of a free and open system” for its own
benefit. This makes its threat
comparable to a virus, which enters into a system and uses the resources of its
host against that host. “And you do not
fight this kind of enemy by shooting at it. You respond by strengthening the
capacity of the system to prevent the virus and strengthen its immunity.”[64]
Even if the
community policing model can be manipulated and abused,[65]
what
distinguishes it from military strategies is --once again-- that committing
greater resources will make police more attuned to community needs and make
policing less violent over all,[66]
whereas
committing more resources to military strategies will increase their store of
destructive weaponry and tempt soldiers and civilian leaders toward short-cuts
that ignore social needs. The
psycho-social dynamic of policing moves those who invest in it towards less
violence because community policing has always been integral to good policing,
even without the name. What prevents
good police from taking a war footing vis-à-vis the populations they are sworn
to protect is that their relationships are intra-community -- not we-vs.-they
but we-are-they. Community policing
only underscores what was already the case, that any violent consequences to
“them” will be consequences for “us.”
This reduces the chance that violence will desensitize police officers
to further violence, and increases the likelihood that any use of violence will
truly be last resort.
The framework of
community policing, then, is one within which members of both the just war and
pacifist traditions can contribute, and can in fact “provoke one another to
love and good deeds” (Hebrews 10:24).
Any further convergence of the two, however, will require more than
theory or pronouncements, more than right intentions. It will require practices -- a firm pastoral commitment to
engendering and forming communal practices down to the parish level.
I choose the
more Catholic word “parish” here because in the formation of those practices we
need to make war into less-and-less of a church-dividing issue, the Roman
Catholic Church and other representatives of the just war tradition bear a
somewhat greater burden of proof.
“Proof” connotes reason, and the strength of the just war tradition down
through the centuries has been its claim to reason. Reason, reflecting upon common human experience, rightly ordered
through the authoritative teaching authority of the Church, is supposed to have
been strong enough to minimize recourse to war. Yet it is not at all clear that just war thinking has established
enough of a track record of doing so that it really constitutes a communal
(rather than merely intellectual) tradition.
In order to convince pacifists that the just war approach offers a
legitimate resource for Christians, Catholics will need to embody their “proof”
with practices that would transform the just war tradition back into what it
has claimed to be -- in effect, just policing.[67]
If the bearing
of burdens here is asymmetrical, however, it is nonetheless balanced, for
Mennonites in turn bear a somewhat greater burden of charity. The strength of their pacifist tradition
down through the centuries has been its claim to the power of Christ-like
love. It is faith in this power that
leads Mennonite pacifists to hope against hope for the reconciled healing of
relationships in even the most intransigent of human conflicts. Yet it is not at all clear that the
descendents of persecuted Anabaptists have established an adequate track record
of applying this faith and hope for the healing of Christ’s divided
Church. In order to convince Catholics
that their tradition embodies the transformative power of love rather than the
schismatic hardening of resentment, they will need to interpret Catholic
willingness to take on and grapple with the problems of civic governance as
charitably as intellectual honesty allows -- rather than marking down every
instance of the Catholic exercise of civil authority as evidence of corruption,
the “Fall of the Church,” or “Constantinianism.”
Practicing
for just policing, Mennonite
Relative to
their size, Mennonites do already have a remarkable track record of sending
their people to work among the poor around the world, build relationships in nations
labeled “enemy,” return home with lessons for addressing the root causes of
injustice, work behind the scenes at international mediation, launch pilot
projects for the unarmed defense of populations subject to human rights abuse,
and create alternatives to criminal justice procedures to bring restorative not
retributive justice. The challenge that
they face is not so much to establish a track record as to articulate what they
are doing or will do when that very “track” leads to wider institutional~ization
of their initiatives, in some cases by civil authority.[68] Catholics and other Christians with fewer
scruples about participating in the state may legitimately ask, So what will
you do if you win? Are you willing to
help implement the changes for which you have called? Why then is governance not legitimate for Christians? Mennonites have faced this question with varying
degrees of consistency when their own ministries have positioned Mennonites to
take governmental roles in health systems, welfare programs, international
development agencies, and so on. Yet
these state functions already assume the rule of law, made possible through
policing. What if Mennonites now propose
alternative forms of policing itself?
In order to
work at this challenge for other functions of state, Mennonites have increasingly
seen themselves in the role of Jeremiah’s exiles, whom the prophet exhorted to
“seek the shalom of the city” in which they found themselves while
remembering that their primary loyalty was to God and God’s covenant people.[69]
What Mennonites must show in practice in
order to socially embody their arguments, is whether and how the
Jeremianic model provides a convincing response to the legitimate challenge of
governance. Some of Jeremiah’s exiles
were civil officials, after all. If
this is a model for critical engagement with the tasks of structuring and
governing society without Christian officials losing their ethical moorings
within the master narrative of Israel, Jesus, and the Church,[70]
how
will Mennonites guide their members and hold them accountable? What will happen if society’s need for some
kind of policing meets the possibility of non- or less-violent policing --
perhaps because Mennonites have advocated for just policing?
For now,
Mennonites need not answer these questions by commissioning some of their
members to become police officers.
Direct responsibility for showing how Christians can “just” participate
in “just policing,” domestic and international, without once again
rationalizing war, falls upon Christians who have identified with the just war
tradition. What Mennonites must do (and
do before their own acculturation makes the practice even more difficult) is
broadly implement the kinds of accountability groups that Yoder encouraged for
Christians in positions “of relative power in the wider society.” That should not only mean the few Mennonites
who hold administrative positions in government bureaucracies or the even fewer
who hold elected office, but should just as surely mean Mennonites in
corporations, the academy, journalism, law, and other professions. A few Mennonite individuals and
congregations have taken up Yoder’s suggestions in this regard,[71]
but
the practice has not become widespread.
It must yet become so, either for the Jeremianic model of exercising
social responsibility to convince other Christians that it is an adequate
response to the challenge of governance, or for Mennonites to have a basis for
calling Catholics to the practices that will transform just war into just
policing -- or both.
Practicing
for just policing, Catholic
As we have
seen, war would already be less of a church-dividing issue if the Catholic
Church’s just war theory were in fact -- in the fullest communal sense
-- a just war tradition of limiting military action to operations that
credibly resemble police functions, reminding Catholics to resist the claims of
nationalism, training Catholics to interrogate the legitimacy of every
particular war, and expecting Catholics to refuse participation in wars that
fail to meet the just war criteria.
Mennonites and other historic peace churches might still not sign on,
but they would find the tradition far less objectionable. That is why we may begin to chart the
practices needed to make war no longer a church-dividing issue by exploring
what the Catholic Church needs to do to implement the just war tradition, even
though we hope to displace it with a tradition of just policing.[72]
The basic
proposal is quite simple: The Catholic
Church needs practices that are church-wide and parish-deep enough that they
correspond with the magisterium’s teaching that the just war tradition begins
with a strong presumption against violence, allows wars only as an exception,
and does so only in last resort.
Bishops: Whenever
bishops or their local conferences consider making pronouncements concerning
the justice of particular wars, it only seems fair to expect that they will
oppose the war unless arguments in favor of its justice are overwhelming. This means that in “close calls” in which
“reasonable people may differ” in their “prudential judgments” concerning the
justice and advisability of a war, the default mode of the bishops would
logically remain one of opposition.[73]
If anything, the presumption against use of
violence should have led bishops to oblige Catholic consciences to oppose the
war. Thus the “presumption against
violence” would coincide with the “presumption of truth” to be accorded the
magisterium and would translate into communal (not just individual) selective
conscientious objection.
Advisers: The
presumption against violence must also outweigh the less formal and more
cultural presumption that the Church can only be effective at influencing
policy makers if they make enough concessions to “stay in the loop.” Leading Catholic theologians act not only as
advisers to the bishops but as political commentators influencing public
opinion. Once the U.S. administration had resolved to go to war against Iraq in
1990-91, some of these advisers who had raised serious questions about whether
the war would pass the muster of jus ad bellum criteria began to speak
as though it had, no doubt so that they could maintain the access they needed
to urge that they war be waged according to just in bello criteria.[74] For the shaping of public discourse and
Catholic conscience, such shifts undermine the very vibrancy of that
presumption against violence which the Church needs not only to maintain the
principles upon which the just war criteria stand, but to mobilize forms of
Christian opposition to unjust wars that may well be more efficacious than that
“loop.”
Laity: Only when the
default mode of Catholics is the practice of active nonviolence rather than the
uncritical acceptance of the state’s summons to war will the logic of the just
war theory be operative. John Yoder was
only calling Catholics and others to accountability to their own principles
when he insisted that military participation should be at least as rare for Christians
as conscientious objection to the military is today, and that such
participation should always require exceptional justification.[75] For that to happen, of course, the Church’s
institutions of formal and nonformal education must take a lead in training
Catholics in the theory and practice of active nonviolence, and form them in
virtues of courage, patience and love that correspond to that practice rather
than warrior virtues.
Parishes,
colleges and universities: And for that to happen, parish level
resources must be available to encourage Catholic youth who are considering
military service to transfer their desire for adventure, higher purpose and
service of the common good to justice advocacy, conflict resolution, and even
nonviolent peaceforces. Full communion
and moral support for military service -- or eventually, international policing
-- should only be available to those who are willing to pass through a time of
vocational testing akin to both Mennonite accountability groups and Catholic
novitiates. Such testing would require
them to know well the criteria that are currently associated with the just war
theory. It would prepare them to uphold
those criteria even when that means resisting orders. And in line with Augustine’s attempt to insist on right
intentions of love for enemy rather than cruelty and vengeance even in times of
war, candidates who show a disposition toward retaliation or demonization of
enemies would be forbidden from participation in military, police or
international police forces. Meanwhile,
Catholic campuses that host programs such as the U.S.’s Reserve Office Training
Corp would organize their curricula along these lines in the short run, and
become leading think tanks for transarmament to nonviolent civilian-based
defense in the long run. If governments
object to Catholics training their soldiers-then-international-police in this
way, it will only be fair to expect institutional conscientious objection.
Transnationally: Of course,
for all of this to fulfill its promise in the arena of international
peacemaking, Catholics will need venues for taking strategies for nonviolent
action towards the next level, in that defense of the human rights of whole
populations which we currently know as national defense. Until governments invest in the strategies
and institutions of national defense, and thus commit to a process of
transarmament, the Church should explore doing nothing less than developing a
transnational, nonviolent army or peaceforce of its own.[76] The Church should never have forgotten to
recognize itself as history’s archetypical transnational society, together with
Diaspora Judaism, and in keeping with the teaching of early Church Fathers.[77]
Within the Second Vatican Council’s
re-affirmation of the Church as a transnational “Pilgrim People of God” which
has meanwhile renounced direct political control, there is conceptual space for
launching a nonviolent army or peaceforce for that transnational nation which
is the Church. In any case, on many
smaller levels, building on parish/diocesan social justice offices, and making
fuller use of its college/university Justice and Peace Studies programs, the
Catholic Church must take a lead in forming strategic think tanks, action
groups and pilot projects for the nonviolent defense of peoples. Otherwise, Catholic soldiers and
international police stand no chance of fulfilling the criterion of last
resort.
Prophetically: Admittedly,
these proposals assume and add up to a thorough cultural transformation within
the Roman Catholic Church. For to
institutionalize such practices, Catholics will need to act in ways that may be
uncomfortably counter-cultural for them at first. In the context of what Pope John Paul II has called the modern
“culture of death,” there may in fact be no other way to be pro-cultural in the
best and most human sense. But
ultimately such labels are irrelevant at best and misleading at worst. For sometimes the Church is properly
counter-cultural, sometimes properly inculturated, always properly
multicultural, and always a defender of vulnerable human cultures. In every last case, however, Christians can
only know which is the appropriate response when cultural acceptance is the
least of their concerns.
Here too,
Mennonites have gifts to share.
Concluding
Notes on Ecclesial Vocation
Given historic
power imbalances, Mennonites certainly have some legitimate reasons to be
stubborn in defense of what they believe to be the gospel truths of nonviolence. Yet their own commitment to discipleship
should also lead them to embody nonviolent ways of struggling for justice
without creating new injustices or demeaning their opponents, ways of
dissenting without tearing down the very principle of ecclesial authority, and
ways of creatively searching for “third options.” Might all this not include dreaming and working toward fresh
ecclesial models for maintaining a resolute witness for nonviolence within the
Church Catholic?
In charting the
kinds of communal practices that the Roman Catholic Church will need to
engender in order for war to cease being a church-dividing issue, we have
stressed the need for much wider practices to discern, test, and maintain
accountability to lay vocations -- and yet the concept of vocation can be
problematic for Mennonites at this one point.
Putting pacifism into the category of vocation is problematic if it
means the wider Christian Church accepts their pacifism as legitimate only because
it is relegated to the status of vocation.
Mennonites have already encountered the patronizing attitude by which
the 20th century Protestant thinker Reinhold Niebuhr said they were not
heretics, and had a place in the Christian tradition, so long as they accepted
their marginal and socially irresponsible role as living reminders of the
rigorous but impracticable standards of Jesus’ ethic.[78]
They will not be wrong to reject gentler
offers of recognition for their vocation too, if that is what vocation means.
The need to
embody our arguments socially through communal practices, however, suggests the
sense in which it is proper to speak of a pacifist vocation. In a divided Christian Church, we must
presume that history and circumstance have made some gifts, lessons, and words
from the Lord relatively inaccessible to some Christians -- though intended by
God for all. In this situation, the
very vocation of Christian pacifist communities may well be to offer a living,
socially-embodied argument that nonviolence is normative for all. To call this a vocation is not to compromise
the integrity of that very argument, but to name the urgent sense of responsibility
that some community must take on in order to do what will first make it
intelligible, then imaginable, then credible to other Christian communities and
ultimately to the whole, catholic, body.
The question beginning to loom on the horizon is
whether God is giving us any fresh ecclesial models that would allow for taking
the gift of this Mennonite witness into the Catholic Church, rather than
forever witnessing at the Catholic Church. If this is ever to happen, the Catholic part will be to invite
Mennonites into unity in such a way that the invitation promises not to coopt
(at worst) or domesticate (at best) the very gift that Mennonites would bring
into Catholic communion. The Mennonite
part will be to take the very risk that their tradition confesses is the way to
preserve one’s idenity -- the risk that none will gain their life except by losing
it. The ecclesial models for doing this
may themselves not quite be in view, yet waiting for us if only we walk far
enough over the horizon to see what else we must do to reach their
reality. God surely is not calling all
Mennonites to walk forward with Catholics toward the horizon where they might
discover those models. But for a few
us, that too is a vocation.
APPENDIX A:
LIST OF JUST WAR CRITERIA FROM
USCCB PASTORAL LETTER, 1993,
THE HARVEST OF JUSTICE IS SOWN IN PEACE I.B.2
First, whether
lethal force may be used is governed by the following criteria:
·
Just Cause: force may be used only to correct a grave, public
evil, i.e., aggression or massive violation of the basic rights of whole
populations;
·
Comparative Justice: while there may be rights and wrongs on
all sides of a conflict, to override the presumption against the use of force
the injustice suffered by one party must significantly outweigh that suffered
by the other;
·
Legitimate Authority: only duly constituted public authorities
may use deadly force or wage war;
·
Right Intention: force may be used only in a truly just
cause and solely for that purpose;
·
Probability of Success: arms may not be used in a futile cause
or in a case where disproportionate measures are required to achieve success;
·
Proportionality: the overall destruction expected from
the use of force must be outweighed by the good to be achieved;
·
Last Resort: force may be used only after all peaceful
alternatives have been seriously tried and exhausted.
These criteria
(jus ad bellum), taken as a whole, must be satisfied in order to override
the strong presumption against the use of force.
Second, the
just-war tradition seeks also to curb the violence of war through restraint on
armed combat between the contending parties by imposing the following moral
standards (jus in bello) for the conduct of armed conflict:
·
Noncombatant Immunity: civilians may not be the object of
direct attack, and military personnel must take due care to avoid and minimize
indirect harm to civilians;
·
Proportionality: in the conduct of hostilities, efforts
must be made to attain military objectives with no more force than is
militarily necessary and to avoid disproportionate collateral damage to
civilian life and property;
·
Right Intention: even in the midst of conflict, the aim
of political and military leaders must be peace with justice, so that acts of
vengeance and indiscriminate violence, whether by individuals, military units
or governments, are forbidden.
APPENDIX B:
WHAT IF THE ADVOCACY OF CHRISTIAN PACIFISTS SUCCEEDED?
Consider the
following scenario: Let us wildly
assume that the U.S. which was struck in September 11 had political leaders who
had somehow been impressed by the nonviolent victories against tyrants in the
20th century,[79]
become convinced by arguments in favor of civilian-based defense put forth by
political scientists such as Harvard’s Gene Sharp,[80] and had
begun a process of “transarmament” toward increasing reliance on such
strategies.[81]
Such a U.S.
would embark on a sturdier and more authentic course of coalition-building,
taking European and Arab League concerns far more seriously. It would thus recognize the 9-11 strikes as
a tragically late wake-up call reminding Americans that in a globalized world,
true security can only come by building upon interdependence not spurning it,
and by addressing global inequity rather than flaunting it. This imagined U.S. would already have
welcomed and strengthened the institutionalization of international tribunals
for trying cases of genocide and war crimes, rather than bowing out of relevant
treaties.
And while we’re
at it, let’s imagine that Christians in the West had paid far greater attention
to Pope John Paul’s Jubilee Year calls for repentance from historic sins such
as the Crusades, and were communicating far more broadly their remorse and
desire for qualitatively new relationships with the Muslim world.
No doubt all of
this would already have gone far toward removing the causes of terrorism. But proponents of Realpolitik have a
point when they argue that socioeconomic change can never come fast enough to
eliminate all resentment and threats.
So let us concede that the 9-11 strikes could still have
happened. Fortunately, all of this
would also have cleared the way for waging a nonviolent campaign on various
fronts.
While diplomats
appealed to Afghani tribal elders to turn over al Queda leaders to an international
tribunal, culturally sensitive nonviolent practitioners and mediators would
disperse throughout Afghanistan and the Muslim world to communicate Western and
Christian willingness to learn and correct the reasons “why they hate us.” Combined, these efforts would do enough to
begin drying out the social network of support for al Queda that Afghani
leaders would then have the political cover they needed to remove their support
for al Queda.
Still, since
the premise of all these alternative policies is that terrorist crimes against
humanity should be treated within the rubric of prosecuting criminals not
waging war, we must assume that as criminals, the perpetrators would
probably refuse to turn themselves in.[82]
So what now? It actually turns out to be far easier to
imagine the conditions in which societies could dispense with war than it is to
imagine dispensing with the police function.
It is in fact realistic to imagine dispensing with war because
all of the strategies to which I have alluded are in development by theorists
and practitioners employing pilot projects.
Further, global interdependence makes successful military strategies
increasingly unimaginable (if success means proportionately less violence, not
simply winning wars). Yet to complete
the final phase of the scenario I have imagined, some kind of SWAT team with
recourse to lethal violence still seems necessary. So too for the prison guards to hold them. Thus we must press the question of whether
post-9-11 calls for turning to international legal procedures do not imply
positive support for police action.[83]
NOTES
[1].
Second Vatican Council, Gaudium et Spes
[Pastoral Constitution on the Church in the Modern World] (1965), §80.
[2].
John Howard Yoder, The Christian Witness to
the State, Institute of Mennonite Studies Series, no. 3 (Newton, Kan.:
Faith and Life Press, 1964), 47.
[3].
“[W]e cannot fail to praise those who renounce
the use of violence in the vindication of their rights and who resort to
methods of defense which are otherwise available to weaker parties too,
provided this can be done without injury to the rights and duties of others or
of the community itself.” Vatican
Council, Gaudium et Spes [Pastoral Constitution on the Church in the Modern
World], §78.
[4].
“Catholic teaching sees these two distinct moral
responses as having a complementary relationship, in the sense that both seek
to serve the common good. They differ in their perception of how the common
good is to be defended most effectively, but both responses testify to the
Christian conviction that peace must be pursued and rights defended within
moral restraints and in the context of defining other basic human values.” National Conference of Catholic Bishops
(NCCB), The Challenge of Peace: God’s Promise and Our Response
(Washington D.C.: United States Catholic Conference, 1983), §76.
[5].
The United Methodist Council of Bishops, In
Defense of Creation: The Nuclear Crisis and a Just Peace, Foundation
Document (Nashville: Graded Press, 1986), 33, 88.
[6].
John
Howard Yoder, ed. and trans., The Schleitheim Confession, with an
introduction by Leonard Gross (Scottdale, Penn.: Herald Press, 1973), art.
6. Although conservative rather than
activist Mennonites are most likely to quote the Schleitheim Confession today,
many of the very Mennonites who most sought to oppose the “war on terrorism”
looming in September and October of 2001 found themselves reflecting the logic
of Scheitheim nonetheless when (as we will see) they called for alternative,
international, judicial responses to terrorism that still would require some
military or police force to apprehend the criminals.
[7].
Glen Stassen, ed., Just Peacemaking: Ten
Practices for Abolishing War (Pilgrim Press, 1998).
[8].
The
introduction closes with a page and a half of lingering differences and
unfinished business. Only one sentence
on those pages broaches a matter so fundamental that it might have meant
crossing off one of the “ten practices” to make them nine: “We do not all agree with [the] affirmation
of humanitarian [military] intervention” to halt egregious human rights abuses,
“but we think it should be included.” ( Stassen, Just Peacemaking,
26.) This refers to “practice” number
eight, which called for strengthening the United Nations and other
international peacekeeping forces -- military ones -- in order to halt genocide
and other egregious human rights abuses.
[9].
Corroborating this claim on the basis of a much
wider literature review is Tobias Winright, “From Police Officers to Peace
Officers,” in The Wisdom of the Cross: Essays in Honor of John Howard Yoder,
eds Stanley Hauerwas, et al. (Grand Rapids, Mich: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing
Co., 1999), 86, 91-92. A partial
exception was John H. Yoder, who was noting the difference more and more
regularly in the latter years of his career (see for example the emendation to
the revised edition of The Politics of Jesus, 2d ed., reprint, 1972
[Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans, 1994], 205), and encouraging students such
as Winright to pursue its implications at the time of his death. The many references and footnotes to Yoder
in this paper none~the~less only begin to indicate my debt to him, not only
with regard to the question of policing but in his theology of Christian
pacifism and his analysis of the just war tradition. I cannot attribute every idea I might owe to Yoder, not only
because my reading of him spans 25 years, but because I learned his analysis of
the just war tradition less from his writing than from a doctoral seminar on
that topic at the University of Notre Dame.
[10].
Cf. John Howard Yoder, When War is Unjust:
Being Honest in Just-War Thinking, rev. ed., with a foreword by Charles P.
Lutz, with an afterword by Drew Christiansen (Maryknoll, N.Y.: Orbis Books,
1996), 50-70.
[11].
For classic catalogs of the criteria for a just
war, see: Augustine, Contra Faustum Manichaeum [Reply to Faustus the
Manichaean] 1.22.74-76; Aquinas, Summa Theologica II-II 40.1; Francisco
de Vitoria De iuri belli [On the law of war]. John Yoder provided a quite detailed catalog in appendix 5 of the
revised edition of When War is Unjust, 147-61 [note that this is not
available in the first edition, Augsburg Publishing House, 1984]. Also see the 1992 Catechism of the
Catholic Church, ¶¶ 2307-2317, and the U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops,
The Harvest of Justice is Sown in Peace, pastoral letter (Washington
D.C.: United States Catholic Conference, 1993), section I.B.2, Http://www.nccbuscc.org/sdwp/harvest.htm. The Harvest of Justice offers a list
that is commendable for thoroughness yet brevity (see Appendix
A).
[12].
John Howard Yoder, “Peace Without Eschatology?”
in The Royal Priesthood: Essays Ecclesiological and Ecumenical, edited
by Michael G. Cartwright (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1994), 166-67.
[13].
Cf. note 67.
[14].
Nor need we belabor the objections that arise
(in accord with Mennonite pacifist doubts about the reliability of common
sense) as to whether the natural law is universal or accessible enough to guide
us. For a standard version of those
objections, however, see Yoder, Christian Witness to the State, 33-34.
[15].
Augustine, in Ep. 47.5 to Publicola,
provided an argument that a public functionary was no more guilty of homicide
when acting to defend his city against villains who would threaten public order
than the builder of a wall would be if it fell upon someone trying to tear it
down -- but he first took it as axiomatic that a Christian who was not to
defend his own life might “happen to be a soldier or public functionary acting,
not for himself, but in defence of others or of the city in which he
resides.” In City of God 19.6
Augustine began the chapter with a rhetorical question that took civil judgment
and thus policing to be a self-evident
need: “What of those judgements passed by men on their fellow men, which cannot
be dispensed with in cities, however much peace they enjoy?” Once he had established that a just man
would reluctantly sit as civil judge (thus participating in the police
function), Augustine argued that this same man would participate in just wars.
Martin
Luther, in arguing that soldiers could be Christians, exclaimed that if he gave
in on this point he would have to conclude that policing was wrong too ( Martin
Luther, “Whether Soldiers, Too, Can be Saved,” 1526, translated by Charles M.
Jacobs and Robert C. Schultz in The Christian in Society III, vol. 46 of
Luther’s Works, edited by Robert C. Schultz, Helmut T. Lehmann, gen. ed.
[Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1967], 98-99).
Though Luther did go on to refer his readers to another treatise on Temporal
Authority for a fuller explanation, his exclamation suggested a working
assumption the legitimacy of policing was basically self-evident.
[16].
John Calvin, The Institutes of the Christian
Religion, vol. 2, edited by John T. McNeill, translated by Ford Lewis
Battles, The Library of Christian Classics, vol. 21 (Philadelphia: Westminster
Press, 1960), IV.20.
[17].
John Calvin articulated the continuity that many
people take to settle the matter when, after many pages defending the
legitimacy of civic authority, he summarily justified warfare in a few
sentences:
Indeed,
if [kings] rightly punish those robbers whose harmful acts have affected only a
few, will they allow a whole country to be afflicted and devastated by
robberies with impunity? For it makes
no difference whether it be a king or the lowest of the common folk who invades
a foreign country in which he has no right, and harries it as an enemy. All such must, equally, be considered as
robbers and punished accordingly.
Therefore, both natural equity and the nature of the office dictate that
princes must be armed no only to restrain the misdeeds of private individuals
by judicial punishment, but also to defend by war the dominions entrusted to
their safekeeping, if at any time they are under enemy attack.
Calvin,
The Institutes of the Christian Religion, 4.20.11.
[18].
Duane L. Cady, From Warism to Pacifism: A
Moral Continuum (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989).
[19].
As John Yoder once remarked in a seminar, if as
the war realists sometimes say, “war is hell,” there is presumably no morality
in hell. Even if war is not entirely
impervious to morality, as the development of international laws of war
suggests, what matters here is the tendency.
The fragility and tenuous of respect for the norms of international law
amid war only confirms that tendency.
[20].
See Yoder, When War is Unjust, 12-14,
130-35.
[21].
While the rituals surrounding police work
include flags, oaths, and appeals to honor, they manage to proceed in far less
feverish ways.
[22].
As Stanley Hauerwas has said, “B52s turn out to
be very crude police officers.” Jim
Wallis, “Interview with Stanley Hauerwas,” Sojo.Net: The Online Voice of
Sojourners Magazine, January-Februaruy 2002, http://www.sojo.net/index.cfm?action=news.display_archives&mode=current_opinion&article=CO_010702h
John
Yoder made this same point at greater length in Christian Witness to the
State, 46-47:
We
should ... be reminded that as long as an international agency uses war as if
it were police action, it is not a simple extension of the state of Romans 13
to the international level. Even the
smallest and most gentlemanly war strikes more innocent that guilty
persons. For an international system of
courts and coercion to be truly spoken of as police, ways would have to
be found to make its sanctions apply to responsible individuals on the bases of
clearly defined crimes, with individual nations not promising to accept punishment
as a nation but agreeing to extradite any offender, even political leaders, for
trial and eventual punishment. Defining
effective international government in this way is of course setting an
idealistic goal; but it is less idealistic than the idea that military action
could be truly an instrument of justice.
[23].
Wallis, “Interview with Stanley Hauerwas.” The larger context of this quote relates
directly to the larger context of this paper:
Wallis:
... We've done the critique of the bombing and the violence. What about a
global police force?
Hauerwas:
I think a police force is the best institutionalization of what just war should
be about. But then the arresting agent is not the same as the judging agent. In
war, those two are the same. I am extraordinarily sympathetic with the police
in this country, because we take them from a social class usually just above
criminal class, put them in the most complex social situations, and then we
blame them for becoming hardened. Give me a break. What we need to do is to ask
ourselves, "What kind of social cooperation do we need that can make it
possible for people to be called to the police function of the state in a
manner that they will have some confidence that they will never have to kill
anyone?" I'm willing to do that. I'm deeply committed to it as a matter of
fact.
In the international arena, it's even
harder, but I would certainly like to start envisioning the possibility of that
kind of police force. The difficulty is of course police are only legitimated
to intervene in violent contexts where there is a prior legal restraint. I can
arrest you for theft because I know what theft is. The problem in the
international arena is there is not that much law that can give you direction
to know what to do, and the way you've got to build it up is through common
action, but God knows that's going to be a hard matter. I'm certainly willing
to enter into those kinds of discussions and hopefully make some modest
arrangements in that regard.
[24].
For an elegant and historically literate essay
on some of these dynamics, see Lee Sandlin, “Are we Finally Losing the War? /
Losing the War,” two-part series, Chicago Reader, 7-14 March 1997.
[25].
Though adrenaline surely courses through the
veins of police SWAT teams too, and constant exposure to danger and frustration
can lead to police brutality even without factors like racism, war changes the
chemistry in significant ways. The
setting is more likely to be outside of the soldier’s own community, so that
neither bonds of identification or the rule of law constrain the psychology of
frenzy. (Racism and racial disparity
increase the prospect of police brutality precisely because they give police
the sense of being at war with the neighborhoods they are sworn to keep safe). Further, the military campaigns that create
the conditions for frenzy are prolonged so that the conditions become endemic,
whereas the high-intensity occasions for SWAT team police actions are just that
-- occasional.
[26].
Cf. point 1 of the list in the text. That late-20th-century Serbian nationalists
cited a thirteenth-century defeat in order to stoke their sense of heroism
suggests how powerful this phenomenon can be.
But this is only an extreme case of how far the psycho-social dynamics
of real wars can take us from the dispassionate rationality of just war theory
and the practical precision of good policing.
[27].
John H[oward] Yoder, “Surrender: A Moral
Imperative,” The Review of Politics 48 (Fall 1986): 576-95.
[28].
Along with the development of increasingly
lethal technologies of war, this has been the story of modern warfare, whether
we are talking about the creation of mass armies since the French Revolution,
the interpenetration of guerrilla movements with their civilian bases, or
expansion of “military-industrial complexes.”
[29].
Although the various tactics of low-intensity
warfare (creating lightly-armed civilian patrols, engaging in nonmilitary
projects to win over the loyalty of a suspicious populace, etc.) may seem analogous
to community policing, low-intensity warfare weakens the social fabric of
communities by inviting neighbors to inform on one another, or use martial
procedures to settle old grudges.
[30].
For a similar list, overlapping in part with my
own, see Winright, “From Police Officers to Peace Officers,” 102. The two lists are complementary not
competitive because Winright’s focuses on differences in legal status, while
mine focuses on what I am calling psycho-social dynamics. Also note Yoder, The Politics of Jesus,
205.
[31].
Note for example the passing statement by Drew
Christiansen SJ in a 1999 article in the context of Kosovo bombing: “Clarity
and certainty are far less easy to attain today on the ethics of using force
than at times when the international system was more stable.” Might this point to yet another
psycho-social dymanic, by which the more policy-makers need the just war
tradition, the less likely it is to provide them with clear guidance? See Drew Christiansen, S.J., “Peacemaking
and the Use of Force: Behind the Pope’s Stringent Just-War Teaching,” America,
15 May 1999, 13-18.
[32].
On the origins of modern, separate, police
forces in the 19th century, see Winright, “From Police Officers to Peace
Officers,” 87-89.
[33].
Stanley Hauerwas has since sought repeatedly to
remind U.S. Christians of that (see quotation, e.g. in Jim Wallis, “Hard
Questions for Peacemakers,” Sojourners, January-February 2002, 32; http://www.sojo.net/index.cfm?action=magazine.article&issue=soj0201&article=020112). I would add that Christians will be even
less likely to buy the cliche that Sept. 11 changed everything if they practice
the preferential option for the poor and the virtue of solidarity well enough
to know that most of the world suffers many things but no illusion of
invulnerability, and if they remember that Jesus never promised his followers
freedom from pain and death except on the other side of cross-bearing. As I wrote to a struggling student in the
following days, Christian pacifists who are truly committed to Jesus’
nonviolence will not abandon that commitment just because the enemy they are
called to love turns out to be a lot nastier than they expected.
[34].
In a report to the MCC Peace Committee meeting
in Winnipeg, November 26-27, Daryl Byler of the Mennonite Central Committee
(MCC) Washington Office noted that he had already begun taking this approach
within days of the attack. A few weeks
later, on October 15, the Mennonite Church USA Peace and Justice Committee
issued a “Statement to Mennonite Congregations” along similar lines. Appropriate to the focus that Mennonite
social ethics has on the distinctive witness of the Christian community itself,
the statement expanded most upon personal and congregational ways of praying
and working for peace. Those not only
included calling “on our government to address the root causes of the problem,”
however, but also encouraging “the governments of the world to use the existing
mechanisms of the United Nations Security Council and world court system to
deal with the present crisis.
[35].
Friesen is author of Christian Peacemaking
& International Conflict: A Realist Pacifist Perspective and professor
at Bethel (KS) College. At a campus
forum already on the afternoon of Sept. 11 he prepared a handout for a campus
forum held the day of the attack, which has since been published as a sidebar
in an MCC publication. See “Naming What
Happened and How we Respond,” Peace Office Newsletter 32, no. 1
(April-June 2002): 7.
[36].
Lederach is Professor of International
Peacebuilding at Notre Dame’s Kroc Institute for International Peace Studies.
[37].
John
Paul Lederach, “Quo Vadis? Reframing Terror from the Perspective of Conflict
Resolution,” Town Hall Meeting (University of California, Irvine, 2001), http://www.nd.edu/~krocinst/sept11/ledquo.html. Also see John Paul Lederach, “The Challenge
of Terrorism: A Traveling Essay” (2001), Http://www.mediate.com/articles/terror911.cfm,
and Jim Wallis, “An Interview with John Paul Lederach,” Sojo.Net: The Online
Voice of Sojourners Magazine, January-February 2002, http://www.sojo.net/index.cfm?action=news.display_archives&mode=current_opinion&article=CO_010702l.
[38].
Wallis, “Interview with Stanley Hauerwas.”
[39].
The American Friends Service Committee did
release a paper detailing legal remedies available to the United States through
international courts and tribunals. See
AFSC, “International Legal Remedies in Response to the Attacks of September
11th, 2001” (2001), Http://www.wcc-coe.org/wcc/behindthenews/analysis20.html. It should be noted that the Society of
Friends (Quakers) has been more open than Mennonites to Christian participation
in policing, including international police forces, from their inception. See Guy Franklin Hershberger, The Way of
the Cross in Human Relations (Scottdale, Pa.: Herald Press, 1958), 178-79;
Winright, “From Police Officers to Peace Officers,” 105. Winright cites James F. Childress,
“Answering That of God in Every Man,” Quaker Religious Thought 15
(1974): 25.
[40].
Wallis, “Hard Questions for Peacemakers,” 31.
[41].
“Positive” here would contrast with the “double
negative” logic by which pacifists have sometimes taken a stance that does not
oppose police actions (or military operations more closely approximating
police action) when they fall within the legitimate functions of the state
according to Romans 13.
[42].
For a succinct survey of representative
positions, see Winright, “From Police Officers to Peace Officers,” 96-108.
[43].
Howard Zehr, Changing Lenses: A New Focus for
Crime and Justice, Christian Peace Shelf Selection (Scottdale, Pa.: Herald
Press, 1990).
[44].
Guy Franklin Hershberger, War, Peace, and
Nonresistance, 3d ed., reprint, 1944, Christian Peace Shelf Selection
(Scottdale, Pa.: Herald Press, 1969), 54, 156, 311. Police operations might well be less violent than warfare ( War,
Peace, and Nonresistance, 311; Way of the Cross, 179), and the use
of force within a system of international law and policing might be “much less
objectionable than that now exercised in our world at war,” ( War, Peace,
and Nonresistance, 174) but Hershberger was sure that the basic task of the
police and military was fundamentally the same -- to maintain order using
methods of force that “do not harmonize with the New Testament way of
nonresistance” ( War, Peace, and Nonresistance, 162, 311).
[45] Hershberger, War, Peace, and
Nonresistance, 162. This response
might seem curt or aloof in some contexts, but it grew from Hershberger’s
vision of the Christian community richly contributing people of moral character
and ministries that are always in far shorter supply than are soldiers. Toward the end of a later chapter answering
charges like those of Reinhold Niebuhr that a nonresistant people is socially
irresponsible or even parasitic, Hershberger wrote (252-53):
Perhaps if the Roman people had
directed their energies more to the quiet and unassuming task of building the
local communities where life and national character are created, and less to
those spectacular enterprises which are life consuming, the final story of the
Empire might have been different.
Therefore, the Christian youth of today who would make a permanent
contribution to American life is wise if he understands that the most constructive
work which can be done is not to be found in those glamorous and spectacular
enterprises associated with urban industry, military service, and the affairs
of state, but rather in the quiet and more fundamental task of building the
small Christian community. The
Mennonite youth, in particular, if he is wise, will understand that nonresistant
groups like his own, living the Christian brotherhood type of life which has
characterized them for centuries, are a veritable salt of the earth. No the nonresistant people with their historic
emphasis on religious freedom and community brotherhood are not parasites; they
are making a contribution of first-rate importance to modern society.
[46]
This
was characteristic of Yoder’s lifelong approach (he would not have wanted to
say “methodology”) to theological reflection and ethical discernment. On the implications of this approach for the
specific issue of policing, see Winright, “From Police Officers to Peace
Officers,” 108-14.
[47]
On this last point, see
Yoder, Christian Witness to the State, 36:
Much recent discussion of “Christian
responsibility” has been extremely confusing -- rather than definitely false --
because of its failure to clarify the standards by which such responsibility
should be measured. If these standards
should be understood to signify Christians’ accepting the ultimate priority of
the work of the state over that of the church, then such responsibility would
be treason to their own higher commission.
The validity of our witness to society, including the critical address
to the state and the statesman, hangs on the firmness with which the church
keeps her central message at the center: her call to every man to turn to God
and her call to those who have turned to God to live in love.
[48]
Yoder,
Christian Witness to the State, 12f, 36; The Politics of Jesus,
196-98, 201-02, 203-05.
[49]
See
Yoder, Christian Witness to the State, 28 (and cf. 56) for signals of
Yoder’s willingness even to consider Christian participation in some
government functions. The book as a
whole represents Yoder’s argument for the Christian political advocacy.
[50]
Yoder, Christian Witness to the State, 36. Yoder continued: “The use of force must be limited to the police
function, i.e. guided by fair judicial processes, subject to recognized
legislative regulation, and safeguarded in practice against its running away
with the situation. Only the absolute
minimum of violence is therefore in any way excusable. The state has no general authorization to us
the sword independently of its commission to hold violence to a minimum.” Also see pp. 5, 46-47.
[51]
John
Howard Yoder, The Original Revolution: Essays on Christian Pacifism,
Christian Peace Shelf (Scottdale, Pa.: Herald Press, 1971), 74f; Yoder, “Peace
Without Eschatology?” 159-60; self-quoted in Yoder, Christian Witness to the
State, 5.
[52]
Yoder,
Christian Witness to the State, 56-57.
[53]
The
logic of Yoder’s position is a kind of triple negative: Christian policing was not unthinkable,
but he was not yet convinced, so three negatives calculated out to a
continuing negative. And even if he
were convinced, a double-negative could never mean unqualified affirmation.
[54]
Yoder, Christian Witness to the State, 57.
[55]
Stanley Hauerwas has begun charting a way that Christians who accept Yoder’s
theological ethic might nonetheless affirm a version of natural law. Hauerwas argues in With the Grain of the
Universe: The Church’s Witness and Natural Theology, Gifford Lectures
delivered at the University of St. Andrews in 2001 (Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos
Press, 2001) for a natural theology that is not autonomous from but rather
enclosed within the yet-prior claims of Christology. While drawing most explicitly on Karl Barth, Hauerwas’s With
the Grain of the Universe honors Yoder by pursuing Yoder’s own hints that
it is only unbelief which prevents us from seeing that the cross does “run with
the grain” of all God’s creation after all. For the source of that title
phrase, see John Howard Yoder, “Armaments and Eschatology,” Studies in Christian
Ethics 1, no. 1 (1988): 58; Yoder, The Politics of Jesus, 246.
[56]
Cf.
John Howard Yoder, Christian Attitudes to War, Peace, and Revolution a
Companion to Bainton (Elkhart, Ind.: Dist. by Co-op Bookstore, 1983), 31,
34.
[57]
All
quotations in this paragraph are from John Howard Yoder, “The Biblical Mandate
for Evangelical Social Action,” in For the Nations: Essays Public and
Evangelical (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1997), 186-87. For a far more extensive exposition of
Yoder’s conception of Christian congregational discernment and discipline, see
John Howard Yoder, “Binding and Loosing,” in The Royal Priesthood: Essays
Ecclesiological and Ecumenical, edited by Michael G. Cartwright (Grand Rapids,
Mich.: Eerdmans, 1994), 323-58.
[58] See Winright, “From Police Officers to Peace Officers,” 92-96, drawing on the work of Ralph B. Potter and Edward A. Malloy.
[59]
Winright,
“From Police Officers to Peace Officers,” 106
This trend was one factor in the shift we have already seen as Yoder
moved away from Hershberger’s categorical rejection of Christian participation
in both domestic and international policing.
Of course, the development of politically efficacious nonviolence has also
been a factor leading the Roman Catholic magisterium toward an increasingly
stringent application of the just war theory, according to Drew Christiansen
S.J. See Christiansen, “Peacemaking and
the Use of Force: Behind the Pope’s Stringent Just-War Teaching.”; “What is a
Peace Church?: A Roman Catholic Perspective,” paper presented at the
International Mennonite-Roman Catholic Dialogue (Karlsruhe, Germany,
2000).
[60] Gaudium et Spes §80.
[61]
David H. Bayley, Police for the Future, Studies in Crime and Public
Policy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994); James Chacko and Stephen E.
Nancoo, Community Policing in Canada, edited by James Chacko (Toronto:
Canadian Scholar’s Press, 1993); Robert R. Friedmann, Community Policing:
Comparative Perspectives and Prospects (New York: St. Martin’s Press,
1992); Stephen J. Gaffigan and the Community Policing Consortium, Understanding
Community Policing: A Framework for Action (Washington, D.C.: Bureau of
Justice Assistance, 1994); Jack R. Greene and Stephen D. Mastrofski, Community
Policing: Rhetoric or Reality, edited by Jack R. Greene (New York: Praeger,
1988); Kenneth J. Peak and Ronald W. Glensor, Community Policing and Problem
Solving: Strategies and Practices (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall,
1996); Robert C. Trojanowicz and Bonnie Bucqueroux, Community Policing: A
Contemporary Perspective (Cincinnati, Ohio: Anderson Pub. Co., 1990);
Robert C. Trojanowicz and Bonnie Bucqueroux, Community Policing: How to Get
Started (Cincinnati, Ohio: Anderson Pub. Co., 1994); Robert C. Wadman, Community
Wellness: A New Theory of Policing, A PERF Discussion Paper (Washington,
D.C.: Police Executive Research Forum, 1990).
[62]
Christopher Freeman Adams, “Fighting Crime by Building Moral Communities,” The
Christian Century 111, no. 27 (5 October 1994): 894.
[63]
Lederach,
“Quo Vadis?”
[64]
Lederach, “Challenge of Terrorism.”.
Lederach continued: “It is an ironic fact that our greatest threat is
not in Afghanistan, but in our own backyard. We surely are not going to bomb
Travelocity, Hertz Rental Car, or an airline training school in Florida. We
must change metaphors and move beyond the reaction that we can duke it out with
the bad guy, or we run the very serious risk of creating the environment that
sustains and reproduces the virus we wish to prevent.”
[65]
Admittedly,
military strategists and just war thinkers have attempted pale versions of community
policing when they have turned to “low-intensity warfare” replete with public
works to “win the hearts and minds” of populations who might be harboring
clandestine adversaries, or when they air-dropped food aid into
Afghanistan. But if Lederach’s
recommendation is to strengthen the viral immune system of the international
body politic, then public works programs coordinated with low-intensity warfare
are like sending an impoverished patient home after a shortened hospital stay
because she does not have health insurance.
And the air-drops over Afghanistan were like using antibiotics to treat
a viral infection, which every physician knows to be a useless
misdiagnosis.
[66]
In
personal correspondence (4 February 2002) in response to the draft of a
preliminary paper I had written on the question of policing, J. Denny Weaver
noted the potential of “a larger but unarmed police force. If it was known that police were unarmed,
the perpetrators would know that they did not need weapons. And larger numbers
of police would bring more chances to observe, embarrass perpetrators, as well
as do the kind of restorative work that would change people so that they did
not do bad stuff. Of course, a larger (unarmed) police force would cost more
money for salaries and training. But the fact that it will not be considered
because of money still shows that there are other options between doing nothing
and advocating violence.”
[67]
The
notion of and need for socially embodied arguments is a major theme in the work
of Catholic philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre, carried through his books After
Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, 2d ed. (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of
Notre Dame Press, 1984); Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame,
Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988) and Three Rival Versions of
Moral Enquiry: Encyclopedia, Genealogy, and Tradition, The Gifford Lectures
1988 (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990). One of the most succinct statements of
MacIntyre’s case, however, is also one of the sources of this terminology:
Alasdair MacIntyre, “The Privatization of Good: An Inaugural Lecture,” The
Review of Politics 32 (1990): 344-61, especially pp. 356-61.
In the context of ecumenical
dialogue, proofs embodied in practices are especially necessary if Catholics
hope to convince Mennonites of their claims, since Mennonites have sometimes
called discipleship the “essence of Christianity.” (See Harold S. Bender, “The Anabaptist Vision,” Church History
13 [March 1944]: 3-24.)
[68].
For a broader theological discussion of this
question, see Gerald W. Schlabach, “Deuteronomic or Constantinian: What is the
Most Basic Problem for Christian Social Ethics?” in The Wisdom of the Cross:
Essays in Honor of John Howard Yoder, eds Stanley Hauerwas, Chris K.
Huebner, Harry Huebner, and Mark Thiessen Nation (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans,
1999), 449-71.
[69].
John Yoder increasingly explained his
understanding of how Christians should serve the world within the rubric of
this “Jeremianic” model for being a diaspora people that needs neither
territory to maintain its identity nor control of state to render its service
“for the nations” ( John Howard Yoder, For the Nations: Essays Public and
Evangelical [Grand Rapids, Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1997],
1-4, 41-42, 51-78.) Mennonite Central
Committee executives used this image to articulate their position following the
events of September 11, 2001 (See page 7).
[70].
I.e., without allowing public office to become
“autonomous as a source of moral guidance,” as Yoder put it ( “The Biblical
Mandate,” 186) .
[71].
I myself recognized that the time had not yet
come for me to become Roman Catholic, but did accept my current position at a
Catholic university, in consultation with an ad hoc “discernment group” of this
nature.
[72].
I wish to thank Professor Todd Whitmore of the
University of Notre Dame for stimulating many of the proposals that follow by
sharing in personal conversation some of his own ideas for a far more thorough
study of what the Roman Catholic Church must do to operationalize the just war
theory. Dr. Whitmore should not be assumed
to concur with all the particulars of my own proposals, of course, particularly
since our conversation took place a few years ago.
[73].
In the months of late 1990 that led up to Gulf
War against Iraq, for example, this is precisely what did not
happen. The bishops lacked a
“sufficiently clear consensus" to declare the war unjust, admitted
Archbishop John Roach of Minneapolis-St. Paul, chairman of the bishops'
international policy committee; though they did offer appropriate warnings that
according to Catholic teaching war must always be limited, some bishops
condemned the war and others called it justifiable. ( John Dart, “U.S. Bishops Split on War’s Morality,” Los
Angeles Times, 26 February 1991, A-11.)
This, however, meant that as a body they had in effect deferred to the
judgment of government policymakers.
[74].
I recall Fr. Bryan Hehir posing the rhetorical
question about whether to make such a tactical shift in a lecture at the
University of Notre Dame at the time of the Persian Gulf War. Corroborating this recollection is the
article he wrote soon after the war began: “The Moral Calculus of War,” Commonweal
118, no. 4 (22 February 1991): 125-26. The
article charts his moral deliberation step-by-step, as the public debate
shifted from why to when to how questions.
[75].
Yoder, Christian
Witness to the State, 57. See p. 10 above.
[76].
Such an enterprise is more realistic than first
blush may suggest. For in an era of
globalization, political scientists recognize that nation-states are already
ceding some of their prominence as international actors not only to
corporations but to the network of nongovernmental organizations that
constitute the best hope for the kind of global civil society that Catholic
social teaching calls for in the name of human solidarity.
[77].
Epistle of Mathetes to Diognetus
5-6; Shepherd of Hermas sim. 1; Clement of Alexandria, Stromata 6.5-6;
Tertullian, The Apology, 38; Origen, Against Celsus 8.75; Pontius
the Deacon, The Life and Passion of Cyprian 11; Gregory Nazianzen
(recounting the interrogation of Basil the Great), Oration 43.49;
Augustine, City of God 19.17 and 19.26.
[78].
Reinhold
Niebuhr, “Why the Christian Church is not Pacifist,” in Christianity and
Power Politics (New York: Charles Scibner’s Sons, 1940), 1-32.
[79].
India, KKK terrorists in the U.S., Philippines,
Poland, Czechoslovakia, the Soviet Union, South Africa, etc.
[80].
Gene. Sharp, Making Europe Unconquerable: The
Potential of Civilian-Based Deterrence and Defence (Cambridge, Mass.:
Ballinger Pub. Co., 1985).
[81].
In this context, everything that the actual
Washington leadership has said about terrorism constituting a new kind of
threat and requiring a new kind of war would mean something very different but
be more not less appropriate!
[82].
Theorists of nonviolence themselves have
stressed that their strategies do not require the conversion of adversaries
--though they do leave open that possibility in a way that violent action does
not-- but rather aim at altering the system of social supports that allows
adversaries the power to continue committing their injustices.
[83].
“Positive” here would contrast with the “double
negative” logic by which pacifists have sometimes taken a stance that does not
oppose police actions (or military operations more closely approximating
police action) when they fall within the legitimate functions of the state
according to Romans 13.